Nonfiction:
Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, 1979
Consequences of Pragmatism: Essays, 1972–1980, 1982
Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, 1989
Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, 1991
Essays on Heidegger and Others, 1991
Truth, Politics, and “Postmodernism,” 1997
Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century America, 1998
Truth and Progress, 1998
Against Bosses, Against Oligarchies: A Conversation with Richard Rorty, 1998
Philosophy and Social Hope, 1999
Edited Texts:
The Linguistic Turn: Recent Essays in Philosophical Method, 1967, enlarged 1992
Exegesis and Argument: Essays in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory Vlastos, 1973 (with Edward N. Lee and Alexander Mourelatos)
Philosophy in History: Essays on the Historiography of Philosophy, 1984 (with J. B. Schneewind and Quentin Skinner)
Richard McKay Rorty was one of the most controversial figures in the world of American philosophy. He is the son of James Hancock Rorty and Winifred Raushenbush Rorty, two disaffected communists who remained ardent socialists. He was fifteen when he entered the University of Chicago, where he found the atmosphere stuffy with Mortimer Adler’s Aristotelian absolutism. He studied a variety of philosophies, including John Dewey’s pragmatism, which became the foundation of Rorty’s radical philosophy. He earned his B.A. and M.A. there and his Ph.D. at Yale University. Rorty’s teaching career included positions at many prestigious universities: Yale, Wellesley, Princeton, the University of Virginia, and Stanford, where he began teaching in 1998 with a double appointment as professor of philosophy and professor of comparative literature. Rorty married Amelie Sarah Oskenberg in 1954, and they had one son before they were divorced in 1972. Mary R. Varney became Rorty’s second wife in 1972; they have two children. He has been the recipient of several grants and fellowships, including a Guggenheim Fellowship (1973-1974), MacArthur Fellowship (1981-1986), and a grant from the National Endowment for the Humanities (1990-1991). Rorty retired from his position at Stanford in 2006, but continued to live on the campus until his death from pancreatic cancer in 2007.
From early in his career, Rorty was interested in the history and methodology of philosophy. In his introduction to The Linguistic Turn, a book he also edited, Rorty focused on the metaphilosophical difficulties of linguistic philosophy. Two decades later, in Philosophy in History, which he coedited, Rorty divided the history of philosophy into four genres: accounts that treat a given philosopher, school, or period in context and without much reference to earlier or later developments; accounts that treat a given philosopher, school, or period in the light of subsequent “improvements” in philosophy; accounts that analyze the assumptions of a given philosopher, school, or period to discover their purposes; and accounts that treat philosophers of all schools and periods with reference to a few perennial philosophical problems.
Rorty’s methodological and historical bent is evident in his two most important works, Consequences of Pragmatism and Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. The former work attempts to revive American pragmatism of the kind practiced by John Dewey and William James as a happy medium between analytic philosophy and continental philosophy. It is the latter work, however, that assured Rorty of a respected place among modern philosophers and made him the center of a decade-long debate.
Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature is an eminently readable book, especially for those who are not philosophers. This readability is most fitting, since Rorty argues in the book for a more practical, less professional approach to philosophy. He explains that all modern philosophy is based on a representational model for thought derived primarily from three philosophers: John Locke, René Descartes, and Immanuel Kant. Their emphasis on epistemology, Rorty claims, resulted from their successful attempt to free philosophy from the constraints of theology. In other words, he sees the Enlightenment as a response to cultural needs rather than to the nature of reality. Rorty identifies three philosophers–he calls them the three greatest philosophers of the twentieth century–who recognized and responded to the flaws in the philosophical“mirror” of the Enlightenment: Martin Heidegger, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Dewey. Heidegger, Rorty says, created new categories for philosophy to replace the bankrupt terms of Cartesianism. Wittgenstein, in like manner, debunked the myth of the neutrality of science and scientific terminology. Dewey represents, for Rorty, the model of philosophy in the future, a model that will require that philosophy continue its search for knowledge without aggrandizing itself and with full awareness that it is satisfying its own self-interest in the process. The result will be a philosophy that is, to use Rorty’s terms, “edifying” rather than “systematic.”
Rorty was not, however, satisfied with Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, in which he searched for a “single vision”–essentially a Platonic project. To deal with this problem he made a deeper commitment to Deweyan pragmatism by writing Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, in which he argued for a middle ground or a synthesis between Jean-Paul Sartre and Marcel Proust: a nihilistic project that has no single vision in philosophy or life.
Rorty’s work became a kind of self-fulfilling prophecy in the world of professional philosophy, creating a revolution in which members of all camps have taken every effort to maintain and fortify their positions, with the result of a quantum leap in the intensity and clarity of discussion. Rorty also became associated, by virtue of his historicist approach, with the school of literary criticism called deconstruction, which held sway over academic literary circles from 1970 through the mid-1980’s.
In the 1990’s, Rorty published a series of essay collections subtitled Philosophical Papers. His political philosophy came to the fore in Achieving Our Country, in which he describes the differences between what he calls the Old Left, reflecting ongoing reformist impulses, and the New Left, critical of America’s past sins, such as slavery and the Vietnam War, but complicit with the Right in that it has abandoned political argument in favor of cultural issues. Philosophy and Social Hope, a collection of both old and new essays, articulates Rorty’s brand of pragmatism: For Rorty, what mattered was not whether his ideas reflected reality but how useful they were in achieving practical ends such as building a better, more democratic society. In Philosophy and Social Hope, Rorty also responds to criticism reflected in the unfortunate and inaccurate characterization of his work as “postmodern relativist.”